Peirce and Wittgenstein on Common Sense

Detalhes bibliográficos
Autor(a) principal: Leo, Rossella Fabbrichesi
Data de Publicação: 2013
Tipo de documento: Artigo
Idioma: eng
Título da fonte: Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)
Texto Completo: https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/13199
Resumo: I intend to start from Peirce’s idea that precision and certainty have different meanings: “it is easy to be certain – he writes – one has only to be sufficiently vague” (CP 4.237). Certainty is not a result of inquiry, but a premises of it, and so it is connected with vagueness and uncertainty. Its value doesn’t belong to the order of argumentative discourse, but of pragmatic habits. Wittgenstein in On certainty reaches a similar conclusion. Both Peirce and Wittgenstein resolve, thus, a typical Cartesian theme, that of certainty, in a totally anticartesian sense. At the same time, they seem to recuperate some Cartesian topics. Indubitable evidence, lume naturale, instinctive insight and primary knowledge are common notions to both the authors that, nonetheless, maintain the totally antiintuitionistic, antidualist and antimentalistic account from which their philosophies rose. I will analyze some propositions from On certainty by Wittgenstein and will show how close are they to some of the leading propositions of Peirce’s ’68 writings. We begin with all our prejudices, writes Peirce, that “does not occur to us can be questioned” (W2:212); the “play of doubting already presupposes certainty”, goes on Wittgenstein (C 115). Our common sense guides us through practice, leading us to be sure of many things, without a real justification. So there is a certainty which we comply with, that goes beyond truth and falsity, that is not a way of seeing, but a way of acting, as Wittgenstein says. And, as any pragmatic habit, it is immediate and in some sense final (remember that habit is the Final Logical Interpretant). Yet, as far as we try to explain the reasons of our beliefs, our certainty becomes vague, and so uncertain, and the play of infinite semiosis begins.
id PUC_SP-15_75ebf79b79ca5d36cf3ddcf3cae28211
oai_identifier_str oai:ojs.pkp.sfu.ca:article/13199
network_acronym_str PUC_SP-15
network_name_str Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)
repository_id_str
spelling Peirce and Wittgenstein on Common SensePeirce e Wittgenstein acerca do Senso ComumCertaintyVaguenessCommon SenseDoubtBeliefPragmaticsCertezaVaguezaSenso ComumDúvidaCrençaPragmáticaI intend to start from Peirce’s idea that precision and certainty have different meanings: “it is easy to be certain – he writes – one has only to be sufficiently vague” (CP 4.237). Certainty is not a result of inquiry, but a premises of it, and so it is connected with vagueness and uncertainty. Its value doesn’t belong to the order of argumentative discourse, but of pragmatic habits. Wittgenstein in On certainty reaches a similar conclusion. Both Peirce and Wittgenstein resolve, thus, a typical Cartesian theme, that of certainty, in a totally anticartesian sense. At the same time, they seem to recuperate some Cartesian topics. Indubitable evidence, lume naturale, instinctive insight and primary knowledge are common notions to both the authors that, nonetheless, maintain the totally antiintuitionistic, antidualist and antimentalistic account from which their philosophies rose. I will analyze some propositions from On certainty by Wittgenstein and will show how close are they to some of the leading propositions of Peirce’s ’68 writings. We begin with all our prejudices, writes Peirce, that “does not occur to us can be questioned” (W2:212); the “play of doubting already presupposes certainty”, goes on Wittgenstein (C 115). Our common sense guides us through practice, leading us to be sure of many things, without a real justification. So there is a certainty which we comply with, that goes beyond truth and falsity, that is not a way of seeing, but a way of acting, as Wittgenstein says. And, as any pragmatic habit, it is immediate and in some sense final (remember that habit is the Final Logical Interpretant). Yet, as far as we try to explain the reasons of our beliefs, our certainty becomes vague, and so uncertain, and the play of infinite semiosis begins.Pretendo começar da idéia de Peirce de que precisão e certeza têm significações diferentes: “é fácil estar certo – ele escreve – só é necessário ser suficientemente vago” (CP 4.237). Certeza não é um resultado de inquirição, mas uma premissa dela e, assim sendo, está ligada à vagueza e à incerteza. Seu valor não pertence à ordem do discurso argumentativo, mas de hábitos pragmáticos. Wittgenstein, em Sobre a Certeza, alcança uma conclusão similar. Peirce e Wittgenstein, ambos resolvem, assim, um tema cartesiano típico, o da certeza, em um sentido totalmente anticartesiano. Ao mesmo tempo, eles parecem recuperar alguns tópicos anticartesianos. Evidência indubitável, lume naturale, insight instintivo e conhecimento primário são noções comuns a ambos os autores, que, não obstante, mantêm a abordagem totalmente antiintuicionista, antidualista e antimentalista da qual suas filosofias surgiram. Analisarei algumas proposições de Sobre a Certeza, de Wittgenstein, e mostrarei quão próximas elas estão de algumas das principais proposições dos escritos de Peirce de 1868. Começaremos com todos os nossos preconceitos, escreve Peirce, que “não nos ocorrem possam ser questionados” (W2: 212); o “jogo de duvidar já pressupõe a certeza”, continua Wittgenstein (C 115). Nosso senso comum nos guia através da prática, levando-nos a estar certos de muitas coisas, sem uma justificativa real. Há, então, uma certeza, com a qual aquiescemos, que vai além da verdade e da falsidade, que não é um jeito de ver, mas um jeito de agir, como Wittgenstein diz. E, como qualquer hábito pragmático, é imediato e, em algum sentido, final (lembre-se de que o hábito é o Interpretante Lógico Final). Sem embargo, tanto quanto tentemos explicar as razões de nossas crenças, nossa certeza se torna vaga e, portanto, incerta, e o jogo da semiose infinita começa.Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo2013-01-11info:eu-repo/semantics/articleinfo:eu-repo/semantics/publishedVersionapplication/pdfhttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/13199Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; Vol. 5 No. 2 (2004); 58-71Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; v. 5 n. 2 (2004); 58-712316-52781518-7187reponame:Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)instname:Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)instacron:PUC_SPenghttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/13199/9719Copyright (c) 2013 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccessLeo, Rossella Fabbrichesi2024-07-01T13:09:30Zoai:ojs.pkp.sfu.ca:article/13199Revistahttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofiaPRIhttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/oairevcognitio@gmail.com2316-52781518-7187opendoar:2024-07-01T13:09:30Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) - Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)false
dc.title.none.fl_str_mv Peirce and Wittgenstein on Common Sense
Peirce e Wittgenstein acerca do Senso Comum
title Peirce and Wittgenstein on Common Sense
spellingShingle Peirce and Wittgenstein on Common Sense
Leo, Rossella Fabbrichesi
Certainty
Vagueness
Common Sense
Doubt
Belief
Pragmatics
Certeza
Vagueza
Senso Comum
Dúvida
Crença
Pragmática
title_short Peirce and Wittgenstein on Common Sense
title_full Peirce and Wittgenstein on Common Sense
title_fullStr Peirce and Wittgenstein on Common Sense
title_full_unstemmed Peirce and Wittgenstein on Common Sense
title_sort Peirce and Wittgenstein on Common Sense
author Leo, Rossella Fabbrichesi
author_facet Leo, Rossella Fabbrichesi
author_role author
dc.contributor.author.fl_str_mv Leo, Rossella Fabbrichesi
dc.subject.por.fl_str_mv Certainty
Vagueness
Common Sense
Doubt
Belief
Pragmatics
Certeza
Vagueza
Senso Comum
Dúvida
Crença
Pragmática
topic Certainty
Vagueness
Common Sense
Doubt
Belief
Pragmatics
Certeza
Vagueza
Senso Comum
Dúvida
Crença
Pragmática
description I intend to start from Peirce’s idea that precision and certainty have different meanings: “it is easy to be certain – he writes – one has only to be sufficiently vague” (CP 4.237). Certainty is not a result of inquiry, but a premises of it, and so it is connected with vagueness and uncertainty. Its value doesn’t belong to the order of argumentative discourse, but of pragmatic habits. Wittgenstein in On certainty reaches a similar conclusion. Both Peirce and Wittgenstein resolve, thus, a typical Cartesian theme, that of certainty, in a totally anticartesian sense. At the same time, they seem to recuperate some Cartesian topics. Indubitable evidence, lume naturale, instinctive insight and primary knowledge are common notions to both the authors that, nonetheless, maintain the totally antiintuitionistic, antidualist and antimentalistic account from which their philosophies rose. I will analyze some propositions from On certainty by Wittgenstein and will show how close are they to some of the leading propositions of Peirce’s ’68 writings. We begin with all our prejudices, writes Peirce, that “does not occur to us can be questioned” (W2:212); the “play of doubting already presupposes certainty”, goes on Wittgenstein (C 115). Our common sense guides us through practice, leading us to be sure of many things, without a real justification. So there is a certainty which we comply with, that goes beyond truth and falsity, that is not a way of seeing, but a way of acting, as Wittgenstein says. And, as any pragmatic habit, it is immediate and in some sense final (remember that habit is the Final Logical Interpretant). Yet, as far as we try to explain the reasons of our beliefs, our certainty becomes vague, and so uncertain, and the play of infinite semiosis begins.
publishDate 2013
dc.date.none.fl_str_mv 2013-01-11
dc.type.driver.fl_str_mv info:eu-repo/semantics/article
info:eu-repo/semantics/publishedVersion
format article
status_str publishedVersion
dc.identifier.uri.fl_str_mv https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/13199
url https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/13199
dc.language.iso.fl_str_mv eng
language eng
dc.relation.none.fl_str_mv https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/13199/9719
dc.rights.driver.fl_str_mv Copyright (c) 2013 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/
info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccess
rights_invalid_str_mv Copyright (c) 2013 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/
eu_rights_str_mv openAccess
dc.format.none.fl_str_mv application/pdf
dc.publisher.none.fl_str_mv Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo
publisher.none.fl_str_mv Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo
dc.source.none.fl_str_mv Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; Vol. 5 No. 2 (2004); 58-71
Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; v. 5 n. 2 (2004); 58-71
2316-5278
1518-7187
reponame:Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)
instname:Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)
instacron:PUC_SP
instname_str Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)
instacron_str PUC_SP
institution PUC_SP
reponame_str Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)
collection Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)
repository.name.fl_str_mv Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) - Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)
repository.mail.fl_str_mv revcognitio@gmail.com
_version_ 1803387420447604736