The permanence of change: Empedocles, Dewey, and two kinds of pluralist metaphysics of force

Detalhes bibliográficos
Autor(a) principal: Stuhr, John J.
Data de Publicação: 2017
Tipo de documento: Artigo
Idioma: eng
Título da fonte: Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)
Texto Completo: https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/31239
Resumo: This paper sets forth three main claims. First, in light of an interpretation of Empedocles’s pluralistic account of nature (as consisting of the four eternal material or root elements of fire, air, earth and water and the two eternal forces of love and strife), I move beyond a longstanding scholarly dispute (between some commentators who interpret Empedocles as holding that there is an endlessly recurring two-part cosmic cycle and others who hold Empedocles as claiming that there is a single positive movement from cosmic separation and manyness to unity and oneness) to the view that love and strife are an integrated cosmic force that constitutes a permanence of change. It is this view that allows Empedocles to embrace the Parmenidean commitment to the permanence of being (and the impossibility of its passing into non-being) and also to affirm the reality (rather than mere appearance) of the many changes evident in our experience. (And it is this view that the Strasbourg papyrus supports.) Second, I am concerned to establish parallels between this metaphysics of forces and the pragmatism of John Dewey, who held that nature is a mix of the precarious and the stable. The point here is not that Dewey and Empedocles hold the same views; they are separated by radically different accounts in biology, physics, psychology, and morality. The point, rather, is that both set forth metaphysical accounts that are at once pluralistic and centrally attuned to change, process, force, and activity. And it is that Dewey heeded Empedocles’s warning not to boast one knows the general nature of things. Third, I want to explain how Dewey’s view might be seen as a development of the philosophy of Empedocles—a development in which the notion of process or force or activity is reconstructed without any teleology and in which the notion of root elements is understood functionally rather than ontologically. I take this to be a movement within the development of metaphysical pluralism from being to becoming—a movement in which an Empedoclean focus on force may prefigure pragmatism and, thus, a way of viewing Empedocles as not merely pre-Socratic but also pre-pragmatic.
id PUC_SP-15_5ae3a94959189fe983c1e5c327bf0575
oai_identifier_str oai:ojs.pkp.sfu.ca:article/31239
network_acronym_str PUC_SP-15
network_name_str Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)
repository_id_str
spelling The permanence of change: Empedocles, Dewey, and two kinds of pluralist metaphysics of forceA permanência da mudança: Empédocles, Dewey e dois tipos de metafísicas pluralistas de forçaJohn DeweyPragmatismMetaphysicsForceEmpedoclesPermanenceChangePluralismPragmatismoForçaEmpédoclesPermanênciaMudançaPluralismoThis paper sets forth three main claims. First, in light of an interpretation of Empedocles’s pluralistic account of nature (as consisting of the four eternal material or root elements of fire, air, earth and water and the two eternal forces of love and strife), I move beyond a longstanding scholarly dispute (between some commentators who interpret Empedocles as holding that there is an endlessly recurring two-part cosmic cycle and others who hold Empedocles as claiming that there is a single positive movement from cosmic separation and manyness to unity and oneness) to the view that love and strife are an integrated cosmic force that constitutes a permanence of change. It is this view that allows Empedocles to embrace the Parmenidean commitment to the permanence of being (and the impossibility of its passing into non-being) and also to affirm the reality (rather than mere appearance) of the many changes evident in our experience. (And it is this view that the Strasbourg papyrus supports.) Second, I am concerned to establish parallels between this metaphysics of forces and the pragmatism of John Dewey, who held that nature is a mix of the precarious and the stable. The point here is not that Dewey and Empedocles hold the same views; they are separated by radically different accounts in biology, physics, psychology, and morality. The point, rather, is that both set forth metaphysical accounts that are at once pluralistic and centrally attuned to change, process, force, and activity. And it is that Dewey heeded Empedocles’s warning not to boast one knows the general nature of things. Third, I want to explain how Dewey’s view might be seen as a development of the philosophy of Empedocles—a development in which the notion of process or force or activity is reconstructed without any teleology and in which the notion of root elements is understood functionally rather than ontologically. I take this to be a movement within the development of metaphysical pluralism from being to becoming—a movement in which an Empedoclean focus on force may prefigure pragmatism and, thus, a way of viewing Empedocles as not merely pre-Socratic but also pre-pragmatic.Este artigo apresenta três argumentos principais. Primeiro, à luz de uma interpretação da concepção pluralista da natureza de Empédocles (como consistindo dos quatro elementos materiais ou de raiz, do fogo, ar, terra e água, e as duas forças eternas de amor e conflito), vou além de uma disputa acadêmica de longa data (entre alguns comentaristas que interpretam Empédocles como defensor  de um infindo e recorrente ciclo cósmico de duas vertentes, e outros que argumentam que Empédocles afirma que existe um único movimento positivo de separação cósmica e multiplicidade para unidade e unicidade) para a visão que amor e conflito são uma força cósmica integrada que constitui uma permanência da mudança. É esta visão que leva Empédocles a assumir o compromisso parmenidiano com a permanência do ser (e a impossibilidade de sua transformação em o não-ser) como também afirmar a realidade (ao invés da mera aparência) das muitas mudanças evidentes em nossa experiência. (E é essa visão que o papiro de Estrasburgo apóia). Segundo, preocupo-me em estabelecer paralelos entre essa metafísica de forças e o pragmatismo de John Dewey, que argumentava que a natureza era um misto do precário e do estável. A questão aqui não é que Dewey e Empédocles tenham a mesma visão: eles divergem em explicações radicalmente diferentes em biologia, física, psicologia e moralidade. A questão, ao invés, é que ambos apresentaram explicações metafísicas tanto pluralistas quanto centralmente afinadas à mudança, processo, força e atividade. E é que Dewey acatou o alerta de Empédocles de não se vangloriar de saber a natura geral das coisas. Terceiro, gostaria de explicar como a visão de Dewey pode ser considerada como um desenvolvimento da filosofia de Empédocles – um desenvolvimento onde a noção de processo ou força ou atividade é reconstruída sem qualquer teleologia, e no qual a noção de elementos de raiz é entendida mais funcionalmente do que ontologicamente. Considero isso um movimento dentro do desenvolvimento do pluralismo metafísico de ser para se tornar – um movimento onde o foco Empedocliano na força pode prefigurar o pragmatismo e, assim, um modo de considerar Empédocles não como simplesmente pré-socrático, mas também pré-pragmático.Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo2017-02-04info:eu-repo/semantics/articleinfo:eu-repo/semantics/publishedVersionapplication/pdfhttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/31239Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; Vol. 17 No. 2 (2016); 349-362Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; v. 17 n. 2 (2016); 349-3622316-52781518-7187reponame:Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)instname:Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)instacron:PUC_SPenghttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/31239/22065Copyright (c) 2017 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccessStuhr, John J.2017-02-04T19:39:25Zoai:ojs.pkp.sfu.ca:article/31239Revistahttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofiaPRIhttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/oairevcognitio@gmail.com2316-52781518-7187opendoar:2017-02-04T19:39:25Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) - Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)false
dc.title.none.fl_str_mv The permanence of change: Empedocles, Dewey, and two kinds of pluralist metaphysics of force
A permanência da mudança: Empédocles, Dewey e dois tipos de metafísicas pluralistas de força
title The permanence of change: Empedocles, Dewey, and two kinds of pluralist metaphysics of force
spellingShingle The permanence of change: Empedocles, Dewey, and two kinds of pluralist metaphysics of force
Stuhr, John J.
John Dewey
Pragmatism
Metaphysics
Force
Empedocles
Permanence
Change
Pluralism
Pragmatismo
Força
Empédocles
Permanência
Mudança
Pluralismo
title_short The permanence of change: Empedocles, Dewey, and two kinds of pluralist metaphysics of force
title_full The permanence of change: Empedocles, Dewey, and two kinds of pluralist metaphysics of force
title_fullStr The permanence of change: Empedocles, Dewey, and two kinds of pluralist metaphysics of force
title_full_unstemmed The permanence of change: Empedocles, Dewey, and two kinds of pluralist metaphysics of force
title_sort The permanence of change: Empedocles, Dewey, and two kinds of pluralist metaphysics of force
author Stuhr, John J.
author_facet Stuhr, John J.
author_role author
dc.contributor.author.fl_str_mv Stuhr, John J.
dc.subject.por.fl_str_mv John Dewey
Pragmatism
Metaphysics
Force
Empedocles
Permanence
Change
Pluralism
Pragmatismo
Força
Empédocles
Permanência
Mudança
Pluralismo
topic John Dewey
Pragmatism
Metaphysics
Force
Empedocles
Permanence
Change
Pluralism
Pragmatismo
Força
Empédocles
Permanência
Mudança
Pluralismo
description This paper sets forth three main claims. First, in light of an interpretation of Empedocles’s pluralistic account of nature (as consisting of the four eternal material or root elements of fire, air, earth and water and the two eternal forces of love and strife), I move beyond a longstanding scholarly dispute (between some commentators who interpret Empedocles as holding that there is an endlessly recurring two-part cosmic cycle and others who hold Empedocles as claiming that there is a single positive movement from cosmic separation and manyness to unity and oneness) to the view that love and strife are an integrated cosmic force that constitutes a permanence of change. It is this view that allows Empedocles to embrace the Parmenidean commitment to the permanence of being (and the impossibility of its passing into non-being) and also to affirm the reality (rather than mere appearance) of the many changes evident in our experience. (And it is this view that the Strasbourg papyrus supports.) Second, I am concerned to establish parallels between this metaphysics of forces and the pragmatism of John Dewey, who held that nature is a mix of the precarious and the stable. The point here is not that Dewey and Empedocles hold the same views; they are separated by radically different accounts in biology, physics, psychology, and morality. The point, rather, is that both set forth metaphysical accounts that are at once pluralistic and centrally attuned to change, process, force, and activity. And it is that Dewey heeded Empedocles’s warning not to boast one knows the general nature of things. Third, I want to explain how Dewey’s view might be seen as a development of the philosophy of Empedocles—a development in which the notion of process or force or activity is reconstructed without any teleology and in which the notion of root elements is understood functionally rather than ontologically. I take this to be a movement within the development of metaphysical pluralism from being to becoming—a movement in which an Empedoclean focus on force may prefigure pragmatism and, thus, a way of viewing Empedocles as not merely pre-Socratic but also pre-pragmatic.
publishDate 2017
dc.date.none.fl_str_mv 2017-02-04
dc.type.driver.fl_str_mv info:eu-repo/semantics/article
info:eu-repo/semantics/publishedVersion
format article
status_str publishedVersion
dc.identifier.uri.fl_str_mv https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/31239
url https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/31239
dc.language.iso.fl_str_mv eng
language eng
dc.relation.none.fl_str_mv https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/31239/22065
dc.rights.driver.fl_str_mv Copyright (c) 2017 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/
info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccess
rights_invalid_str_mv Copyright (c) 2017 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/
eu_rights_str_mv openAccess
dc.format.none.fl_str_mv application/pdf
dc.publisher.none.fl_str_mv Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo
publisher.none.fl_str_mv Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo
dc.source.none.fl_str_mv Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; Vol. 17 No. 2 (2016); 349-362
Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; v. 17 n. 2 (2016); 349-362
2316-5278
1518-7187
reponame:Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)
instname:Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)
instacron:PUC_SP
instname_str Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)
instacron_str PUC_SP
institution PUC_SP
reponame_str Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)
collection Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)
repository.name.fl_str_mv Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) - Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)
repository.mail.fl_str_mv revcognitio@gmail.com
_version_ 1803387421761470464