Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophy
Autor(a) principal: | |
---|---|
Data de Publicação: | 2023 |
Tipo de documento: | Artigo |
Idioma: | eng |
Título da fonte: | Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) |
Texto Completo: | https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/63651 |
Resumo: | The article aims to show that Peirce, after realizing the appropriation that James and others made of Pragmatism, taking it far from an ideal of justice and keeping it in the service of a “nauseating utility”, whose principle was that only individual utility, including spiritual well-being, would be the ultimate goal of all practice, he sought a philosophy that would keep logic and science united in a realistic manner with laws that could be metaphysically real. In this way, he perceived the necessity to transcend the hypothetical considerations incorporated into the sense of the pragmatic maxim, attempting to distance it from nominalist risk. In this process, he took into account two new normative sciences, esthetics and ethics, in addition to logic, so that Pragmaticism, in intelligent criticism, would investigate whether an admirable end of a subject could be pursued in an indefinite and prolonged course of action, without grounding it solely on individual utility, thus replacing the ideal of justice for the renamed Pragmatism, the Pragmaticism. |
id |
PUC_SP-15_f740d0ddd4be444345c7e426366ff33e |
---|---|
oai_identifier_str |
oai:ojs.pkp.sfu.ca:article/63651 |
network_acronym_str |
PUC_SP-15 |
network_name_str |
Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) |
repository_id_str |
|
spelling |
Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophyA relação das ciências normativas e a predisposição para agir na filosofia de Peirce CriticismIdeal of justiceNormative sciencesPragmatismSynechismCiências normativasCriticismoIdeal de justiçaPragamaticismoSinequismo The article aims to show that Peirce, after realizing the appropriation that James and others made of Pragmatism, taking it far from an ideal of justice and keeping it in the service of a “nauseating utility”, whose principle was that only individual utility, including spiritual well-being, would be the ultimate goal of all practice, he sought a philosophy that would keep logic and science united in a realistic manner with laws that could be metaphysically real. In this way, he perceived the necessity to transcend the hypothetical considerations incorporated into the sense of the pragmatic maxim, attempting to distance it from nominalist risk. In this process, he took into account two new normative sciences, esthetics and ethics, in addition to logic, so that Pragmaticism, in intelligent criticism, would investigate whether an admirable end of a subject could be pursued in an indefinite and prolonged course of action, without grounding it solely on individual utility, thus replacing the ideal of justice for the renamed Pragmatism, the Pragmaticism. O artigo objetiva mostrar que Peirce, após constatar a apropriação que James e outros fizeram do Pragmatismo, levando-o para longe de um ideal de justiça e mantendo-o a serviço de uma “nauseante utilidade”, cujo princípio de que somente a utilidade individual, incluindo o bem-estar espiritual, seria a meta final de toda prática, buscou uma filosofia que mantivesse a lógica e a ciência unidas a um modo realista e com leis que pudessem ser metafisicamente reais. Percebeu, dessa forma, a necessidade de transcender as considerações hipotéticas incorporadas ao sentido da máxima pragmática, afastando-a do risco nominalista. Nesse processo, teve em consideração duas novas ciências normativas, a estética e a ética, além da lógica, para que o Pragmaticismo em criticismo inteligente, investigasse se um fim admirável de um sujeito era passível de ser perseguido em um indefinido e prolongado curso da ação, e não atentando somente à utilidade individual, resgatando o ideal de justiça para o renomeado Pragmatismo, o Pragmaticismo. Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo2023-10-27info:eu-repo/semantics/articleinfo:eu-repo/semantics/publishedVersionapplication/pdfhttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/6365110.23925/2316-5278.2023v24i1:e63651Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; Vol. 24 No. 1 (2023): Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia ; e63651Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; v. 24 n. 1 (2023): Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia ; e636512316-52781518-7187reponame:Cognitio (São Paulo. Online)instname:Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)instacron:PUC_SPenghttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/63651/43438Copyright (c) 2023 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccessZanette, José Luiz2023-09-18T10:55:50Zoai:ojs.pkp.sfu.ca:article/63651Revistahttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofiaPRIhttps://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/oairevcognitio@gmail.com2316-52781518-7187opendoar:2023-09-18T10:55:50Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) - Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP)false |
dc.title.none.fl_str_mv |
Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophy A relação das ciências normativas e a predisposição para agir na filosofia de Peirce |
title |
Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophy |
spellingShingle |
Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophy Zanette, José Luiz Criticism Ideal of justice Normative sciences Pragmatism Synechism Ciências normativas Criticismo Ideal de justiça Pragamaticismo Sinequismo |
title_short |
Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophy |
title_full |
Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophy |
title_fullStr |
Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophy |
title_full_unstemmed |
Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophy |
title_sort |
Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophy |
author |
Zanette, José Luiz |
author_facet |
Zanette, José Luiz |
author_role |
author |
dc.contributor.author.fl_str_mv |
Zanette, José Luiz |
dc.subject.por.fl_str_mv |
Criticism Ideal of justice Normative sciences Pragmatism Synechism Ciências normativas Criticismo Ideal de justiça Pragamaticismo Sinequismo |
topic |
Criticism Ideal of justice Normative sciences Pragmatism Synechism Ciências normativas Criticismo Ideal de justiça Pragamaticismo Sinequismo |
description |
The article aims to show that Peirce, after realizing the appropriation that James and others made of Pragmatism, taking it far from an ideal of justice and keeping it in the service of a “nauseating utility”, whose principle was that only individual utility, including spiritual well-being, would be the ultimate goal of all practice, he sought a philosophy that would keep logic and science united in a realistic manner with laws that could be metaphysically real. In this way, he perceived the necessity to transcend the hypothetical considerations incorporated into the sense of the pragmatic maxim, attempting to distance it from nominalist risk. In this process, he took into account two new normative sciences, esthetics and ethics, in addition to logic, so that Pragmaticism, in intelligent criticism, would investigate whether an admirable end of a subject could be pursued in an indefinite and prolonged course of action, without grounding it solely on individual utility, thus replacing the ideal of justice for the renamed Pragmatism, the Pragmaticism. |
publishDate |
2023 |
dc.date.none.fl_str_mv |
2023-10-27 |
dc.type.driver.fl_str_mv |
info:eu-repo/semantics/article info:eu-repo/semantics/publishedVersion |
format |
article |
status_str |
publishedVersion |
dc.identifier.uri.fl_str_mv |
https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/63651 10.23925/2316-5278.2023v24i1:e63651 |
url |
https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/63651 |
identifier_str_mv |
10.23925/2316-5278.2023v24i1:e63651 |
dc.language.iso.fl_str_mv |
eng |
language |
eng |
dc.relation.none.fl_str_mv |
https://revistas.pucsp.br/index.php/cognitiofilosofia/article/view/63651/43438 |
dc.rights.driver.fl_str_mv |
Copyright (c) 2023 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccess |
rights_invalid_str_mv |
Copyright (c) 2023 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 |
eu_rights_str_mv |
openAccess |
dc.format.none.fl_str_mv |
application/pdf |
dc.publisher.none.fl_str_mv |
Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo |
publisher.none.fl_str_mv |
Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo |
dc.source.none.fl_str_mv |
Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; Vol. 24 No. 1 (2023): Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia ; e63651 Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia; v. 24 n. 1 (2023): Cognitio: Revista de Filosofia ; e63651 2316-5278 1518-7187 reponame:Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) instname:Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP) instacron:PUC_SP |
instname_str |
Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP) |
instacron_str |
PUC_SP |
institution |
PUC_SP |
reponame_str |
Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) |
collection |
Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) |
repository.name.fl_str_mv |
Cognitio (São Paulo. Online) - Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo (PUC-SP) |
repository.mail.fl_str_mv |
revcognitio@gmail.com |
_version_ |
1803387422626545664 |